vorticist
lewis/vorticist pound
by Douglas Messerli
“Vorticism and Abstract Art in the First Machine Age,” an
exhibition organized by Richard Cork. Davis and Long, 746 Madison Avenue, New
York, April 1977
Richard Cork Vorticism and Abstract Art in the First Machine Age
(Berkeley: University of California Press,
1976, 1977), two volumes
The reasons for this are many and somewhat
complex. Vorticism, although named by Pound, is difficult as a visual art for
the literary critic to discuss. The language of the art is here just similar
enough to literature that it is tempting for the comparativist to make
metaphorical connections rather than analogous ones, and even the analogies
must too often be superficial. Pound knew little of art, especially painting;
in at least two reviews he wrote, Pound admits his ignorance: writing in The Egoist in 1914, he notes: "It
is much more difficult to speak of painting. It is perhaps further from one’s
literary habit, or it is perhaps so close to one’s poetic habit of creation
that prose is ill gone to fit it.” When he spoke of art, accordingly, he chose
primarily literary terms. Even when discussing sculpture, to which he was innately
more sensitive, Pound quickly shifted from an art critical language to a
literary one, seemingly interchanging the terms of both. And when he was aware
of distinctions, as in much of Gaudier-Brzeska
and in the two issues of Blast,
in an attempt to be inclusive Pound described a theory that remains abstract.
As Cork and others have perceived,
moreover, the theory of Vorticism was often purposefully abstract. The English
Cubists, as they had been called, seized upon Pound’s epithet, not only to
differentiate themselves from what they often misunderstood of Cubist and
Futurist doctrines, but also for purposes of creating personae and publicity,
and out of what might almost be described as a “nationalistic” desire to create
a new and vital English art. Thus,
although the famed puce-colored first issue of Blast was well stocked with manifesto-like statements, taken
together these present—contrary to Lewis’ later assertion—little of a sound art
doctrine in the manner of Gleizes and Metzinger’s Du Cubisme or Apollinaire’s Le
Peintres cubists. With the Vorticist emphasis on personality, however, this
lack of a unified theory should come as no surprise—indeed, perhaps more than
anything else, the disparity of the members of this movement (the first issue
of Blast included work by
non-Vorticists Ford Madox Ford and Rebecca West) assured its short life.
In 1910 Douglas Goldring had printed in The Tramp a letter by the Italian
Futurist F. T. Marinetti entitled “Futurist Venice,” a document which helped to
open English painting to the influences of non-representational art. In March
and April of that year Marinetti lectured in London at the Lyceum Club, and in
November Roger Fry presented the first “Post-Impressionist Exhibition” (the exhibition,
which was actually titled “Manet and the Post-Impressionists,” was held at the
Grafton Galleries from November 8, 1910 through January 15, 1911), which gave
the English public its first glimpse of more advanced styles of contemporary
painting. Yet the art exhibited at this show was obviously not that avant-garde. The most “advanced”
painting in the show was Picasso’s early Cubist work, Portrait of Clovis Sagot, and other artists represented were
primarily of another era: Cézanne, Derain, Gauguin, Van Gogh, Redon, Matisse,
and Seurat. In other words, as of February 1912, when Roger Fry wrote Lewis
inviting him to become a member of the Omega Workshop, Lewis had had little
direct confrontation with Cubism, and Futurism must have been an even more remote
art. The situation was to change somewhat in March 1912 when the Futurists
showed at the Sackville Gallery; and the second “Post-Impressionist Exhibition”
of October 1912 included works by Braque and Picasso which were more
representative of Cubist art. Still, no exhibition in England was entirely
devoted to Cubist art until 1914. By July 1913, when the Omega Workshop opened,
Lewis—while certainly influenced by the new styles—had had little time to
assimilate them. As William Lipke points out, however, the Omega Workshop, with
its emphasis on decorative pattern and motif, gave Lewis and his friends, men
like Frederick Etchells and David Bromberg, an opportunity to experiment with
form (Lipke, Apollo [March 1970]).
Fry was exploring, moreover, his own theories of form; in 1913 he wrote:
I’m continuing my aesthetic
theories and I have been
attacking poetry to understand painting. I want to
find
out what the function of content is, and am developing
a theory
that…[content] is merely derivative of form
and that all the essential
aesthetic quality has to do with
form. (Virginia Woolf, quoting Fry in Roger Fry: A Biography)
Lewis, brilliant synthesizer that
he was, could not but have been influenced by such ideas. Simultaneously he
must have been developing new theories of his own, applying techniques that he
had developed at Omega along with what he had learned from the Futurists and
Cubists. By October, Lewis and his future Vorticist friends were ready for a
break; they left Fry, ostensibly in anger over Fry’s appropriation of a
commission for Omega which belonged to Lewis and Spencer Gore. But, as Cork,
Lipke, and others have indicated, there were reasons underneath:
They “broke away because Roger
Fry did not want to, and
could not satisfy their wish for personal
distinction,
anonymity being a basic principle of workshops founded
to
serve a community ideal." (N. Pevsner, as quoted by Lipke)
This idea is supported to a
degree by a “Round Robin” letter which Lewis and his friends sent to the press.
A public stir resulted, and attention was brought to bear on Lewis and the
future Vorticists. In that letter Lewis and others attacked Fry, as one would
expect, not only for appropriating the commission but on grounds of his and
Omega’s artistic taste. This attack, perhaps more than any document of the
time, indicates not so much Fry and Omega’s sensibility, but what Lewis and his
friends stood in opposition to in art:
As to its tendencies in Art, they
alone would be sufficient
to make it very difficult for any vigorous
art-instinct to
long remain under that roof. The Idol is still Prettiness,
with its mid-Victorian languish of the neck, and its skin is
“greenery-yallery….”
(Lewis, ed. by W. K. Rose, The Letters
of Wyndham Lewis)
Meanwhile, Lewis had obviously decided to
go public in other ways. By November 17 he clearly felt that it was time to
make known—if not his theory—at least his opposition to Futurist art, and that
night, at Marinetti’s second London lecture held at Hulme’s Poet’s Club, Lewis,
Gaudier, Edward Wadsworth, and Hulme heckled the Futurist; they
“counter-putsched,” as Lewis later describe it, “worsting” the “Italian
intruder” at his lecture stand where he stood “entrenched” (quote from Lewis, Blasting and Bombarding).
Yet, as late as January 1914, when Lewis went
to find a publisher for Blast, he
still spoke of the magazine as “a paper somewhat in the lines of the Futurist
manifesto” (Goldring, Odd Man Out).
And although on the evening the future Vorticists met, Lewis argued with C. R.
W. Nevison, probably over Futurism (Nevison, Paint and Prejudice), the advertisements of April 1 and 15 in The Egoist suggest that, while Lewis had
won out as sole editor, a focus for the journal had not yet evolved.
Forthcoming was a manifesto, but of what was unclear. There were to be
discussions of “Cubism, Futurism, Imagisme and All Vital Forms of Modern Art.”
“THE CUBE,” “THE PYRAMID” and the “END OF THE CHRISTIAN ERA” were promised in
capital letters. But there was no mention of a Vortex or of a new art.
At what point Pound actually coalesced the
group by naming it is uncertain, but by July 15, 1914, the Vorticists were
ready to celebrate at a dinner party at the Dieudonné Restaurant, and five days
later Blast 1, “the great magenta
cover’d oposulus,” as Pound described it, was out. If Pound brought the group a
unifying image, it now became evident that Lewis was behind any unifying
thought. The principles of the Manifesto, if one takes a clue from the
advertisement, were probably written prior to the denomination of the Vortex
image and demonstrate the vague and abstract character of the movement in its
early stages. However, once the vortex had given the group a focus, some
theoretical aesthetic principles were asserted.
If one finally sees evidence of a theory
behind Lewis’ previous actions, however, it is a theory still often
contradictory and unrefined. Certain statements were inevitable: “Blast presents an art of Individuals,”
Lewis writes in “Long Live the Vortex!” (Blast
1, p. 8); “Beyond Action and Reaction we would establish ourselves,” begins
the Manifesto (p. 30). These statements and others like them make it clear that
from the beginning Vorticism was a vehicle for publicity, which Lewis later
made even clearer: “Vorticism…was what I, personally, did, and said at a
certain period. This may be expanded into a certain theory regarding visual
art” (Lewis, from the preface to the 1936 Vorticist Exhibition catalogue for
the show at the Tate Gallery, London).
To expand these statements into a theory
is understandably more difficult. Perhaps two statements in part one of Lewis’
definitions of Vortex underlie all others. “Life is the Past and the Future,”
Lewis asserts; “The Present is Art” (Blast
1, p. 147). While these may appear to be simplistic ideas, what they
indicate about Lewis’ theory is extremely important, for they present the
context needed to comprehend not only his theory but his Vorticist art.
What is immediately evident about these
statements is that Lewis has made the Kantian distinction between life and art.
But this separation is not the same as that made a decade or two earlier by the
aesthetes. Art is not, for Lewis, Wilde’s “fascinating lie,” but is reality.
And “the Artist’s OBJECTIVE is Reality,” he writes (p. 139). Reality for Lewis
is not naturalistic; it is not the reality of life. Rather, it is a reality
found only in art, in the abstract. Lewis had, in part, come to these ideas
through the works of Wilhelm Worringer, who in Formprobleme der Gotik proposed three kinds of aesthetic men: “Der
Primitive Mensch”—who perceiving himself in a hostile universe created an
abstract art—“Der Orientalische Mensch”—who perfected the abstraction and moved
to great order—and “Der Klassische Mensch”—who, as Geoffrey Wagner has put it,
“no longer tortured by perception, no more at odds with nature…,” began “to
enjoy life and artistically idealize nature." Obviously, for Lewis the
superior sense of aesthetics was to be found in the Primitive and Oriental
cultures, for “which art came to be an “avoidance of life and a resentment of
nature” (Geoffrey Wagner, “Wyndham Lewis and the Vorticist Aesthetic,” in Journal of Aestehtics and Art Criticism)
One need not go to Worringer, however, for
sources, for Kandinsky’s Über dast
Geistige in der Kunst was reviewed and excerpted in the first issue of Blast, and it is quite evident that
Lewis, like Kandinsky, was seeking the spiritual in art and its abstractions.
Rather than an “imitation, and inherently unselective registering of
impressions,” Lewis is interested in indicating an object’s “spiritual weight”
(Blast 2, p. 25):
The essence of an object is
beyond and often in
contradiction to its simple truth: and literal
rendering in
the fundamental matter of arrangement and
logic will never hit the emotion
intended by unintelligent
imitation….It is always the POSSIBILITIES in the
object,
the IMAGINATION, as we say, in the spectator, that
matters. Nature is of no importance. (Blast
2, p. 25)
Nature had lost is
importance, in Lewis’ thinking, because, as he would later express it, nature
had been completely internalized. Bergson and his popularizer, Spengler, had
converted all of nature into a mental state by claiming that time was human
consciousness in duration:
Chairs and tables, mountains
and stars, are animated into a
magnetic restlessness and sensitiveness, and
exist on the
same vital terms as man. They are as it were the lowest
grade,
the most sluggish of animals. All is alive: and, in that sense,
all is
mental. (Lewis, Time and Western Man)
In this manner, Lewis believed,
modern man had destroyed space:
Dispersal and transformation
of a space-phenomenon into a
time-phenomenon throughout everything—that is
the trick
of this doctrine. Pattern with its temporal multiplicity, and
its chronologic depth, is to be substituted
for the thing,
with its one time, and its spatial depth. (Time and Western Man)
And, without space, man in time
has no tension with which he can define meaning. The present, Lewis asserts,
can only be revealed when it has become “Yesterday,” the past.
For Lewis then life is past and future,
not Bergsonian durée. And art—because
it is utterly different from life—must be the present. Yet, art cannot be
duration. A few lines later in his Blast
definition Lewis makes this clear: “There is no Present—there is Past and
Future, and there is Art.” If Lewis seems here to contradict his previous
statement, it is only because once he has established art as something that
exists in a realm other than nature, he must redefine it in terms other than
time. This new definition of art is implicit in his statement, for if art is
not in time it is obviously something motionless and dead in space; and this is
precisely the reality which art, according to Lewis, defines: in a world given
over to flux, to duration, only art “is able to confer the static on the
objects it apprehends” (Wagner, Wyndham
Lewis: A Portrait of the Artist as the Enemy). As Lewis expresses it, “We
must have the Past and the Future, Life simple, that is, to discharge ourselves
in, and keep us pure for non-life, that is, Art” (Blast 1, p. 147).
So for Lewis the value of the Vortex
image lay not primarily in its associations with energy (although Lewis obviously
recognized an energy in the tension between man and the static center of the
Vortex), but in the paradox that is visual representation of energy is
transformed into stasis:
You think at once of a
whirlpool. At the heart of the
whirlpool is a great silent place where all the
energy
is concentrated. And there, at the point of concen-
tration, is the
Vorticist. (quoted in Violent Hunt, I
Have
This to Say)
In Blast 1 Lewis expresses
this idea in a pun:
The Vorticist is at his
maximum point of energy when
stillest.
The Vorticist is not the
Slave of Commotion, but its
Master
The Vorticist does not suck
up to Life.
Looking back, then, it is easy to see why
Lewis so thoroughly took Futurism to task. While certainly Vorticism took much
from Futurism, especially its “proselytizing attitude,” and while there is
little doubt that Lewis was influenced by the likes of Carrà and Boccioni—both
of whom exhibited in the March 1912 Sackville show—Lewis’s Vorticism is an art
diametrically opposed to Futurism. The Futurists, with their emphasis on
dynamism, with their reliance upon what Lewis calls “the plastic and real,” and
with their subjugation to rhetoric were an anathema to Lewis. “AUTOMOBILISM
(Marinettism) bores us,” writes Lewis (Blast
1, p. 46). “The futurist is a sensational mixture of the aesthete of 1890
and the realist of 1870.” In Futurism Lewis sees that “Art merges in Life again
everywhere.” “Everywhere LIFE is said instead of ART” (Blast 1, p. 28
Lewis’ reactions to Cubism, and especially
to Picasso, are more complex. Throughout Blast,
but particularly in the essay “Relativism and Picasso’s Latest Work,” Lewis
debunks Picasso and Cubism. The latest works which Lewis describes are clearly
Picasso’s collages of 1911-1913, shown perhaps in the 1914 Cubist show. Against
these “small structures in cardboard, wood, zinc, glass, string, etc., tacked,
sewn or stuck together,” Lewis reacts: “Picasso has become a miniature
naturalistic sculptor of the vast natures-morte of modern life. Picasso has
come out of the canvas and has commenced to build up his own shadows against
reality” (Blast 1, p. 139). “The
imitate like children the large, unconscious, serious machines and contrivances
of modern life” (Blast 1, p. 140). In
the second issue of Blast the attack
became broader, as Lewis found fault with Cubism for its link with
Impressionism: “Picasso through the whole of his ‘Cubist’ period has always had
for starting point in his creations, however abstract, his studio-table with
two apples and a mandolin, the portrait of a poet of his acquaintance, or what
not…. The great licence Cubism affords tempts the artist to slip back into
facile and sententious formulas, and escape invention” (Blast 2, p. 146). It is here, I suggest, that Lewis most displays
his confusion and demonstrates what the Vorticist theory lacked.
What Picasso’s new works actually
indicated was what we now call a shift from Analytical to Synthetic Cubism.
Synthetic Cubism represented a movement in the same direction towards which
Lewis was striving. Indeed, Picasso, Braque, and Gris were creating assemblages
that existed for their own sake. As Christopher expresses it, the artist,
through his inclusion of pieces of cloth, chair caning, or paper in the
painting, had “placed it [the painting] in the world of real objects where it
[had] its own existence as a relationship between real things, rather than as a
representation of a set of relationships in nature, which it [was] intended to
communicate in a more or less illusionistic manner” (Gray, Cubist Aesthetic Theories). A statement by Braque in 1917 supports
this:
The bits of glued paper, the
imitation wood and other elements
of the same art which I have employed in some of my
designs,
are equally valid because of the simplicity of these compositional
facts, and for that reason have been confused with illusion,
of which they are the
exact contrary. They too are simple facts,
but they have been created by the mind,
by the spirit, and they are
one of the justifications of a new spatial
figuration. (Braque,
“Pensées et réflexions sur la peinture,” Nord-sud)
Furthermore, these works by Picasso, in
pointing towards Synthetic Cubism—in indicating a shift from what Gray calls “epistemological”
to the “aesthetic” approach—manifested also a shift away from an art in which
the artist played the role of creator of a dynamic reality, to an art in which
“the picture [was] regarded as a synthesis of the artist’s a priori ideas which is given concrete form in painting in order to
take its place as a part of the world of natural forms.” In other words, Lewis
had failed to see in Picasso the evidences of an art applicable to his own
theory.
One can only speculate on the reasons for
Lewis’ failure of perception here, but I suggest that the most obvious ones are
implied by Lewis in the same essay on Picasso:
He no longer so much interprets, as
definitely MAKES nature (and
“DEAD” nature at that).
A kettle is never as fine as a man.
This is a challenge to the kettles. (Blast 1, p. 140)
I think one can perceive in such
statements that, despite his theoretical separation of art and nature, Lewis in
actuality has trouble responding to and creating a non-referential art. Lewis’
art is an intellectual interpretation of
nature, an interpretation that focuses and controls the time of man. In making art, in actually creating a new
combination of objects and forms, Picasso, in Lewis’ thinking, was merely positing
something which would exist in flux simultaneously with nature and which,
because it has no human reference, is dead even in terms of that. In short,
Lewis’ art, even when he turned to pure abstraction, continues to rely upon man
and time for its reference: although diametrically opposed to them, his art of
space is given meaning only insofar as it is separate from life, is something
distinct from man’s future and past. Thus Vorticism, as Lewis theorized on it,
is not a pure art—despite its obvious differences from Futurism, Vorticism like
the Italian movement is a literary art, an art which relies on ideology rather
than on a love of pure form. In the final evaluation, it is an art as reliant
on time as it is upon space. In Lewis’ Vorticism, forms are not permitted to
exist for their own sake but rather become emblems that stand for man’s
confrontation with life.
It is in this context, then, that one
must consider Pound’s poetic theory. But here we must be careful, for although
Pound—who met Lewis in 1910—obviously shared much in his thinking with Lewis,
he simply parroted some ideas without thoroughly understanding their
implications, and, most importantly, there were vital areas where his theory
differed from Lewis’ theory and art.
Surely, as Richard Cork has implied, the
didactic and proselytizing tone of Vorticism was not antithetical to Pound’s
nature; in 1912-13 he had fought almost as vociferously for the Image. But
Imagism had failed him because it had been misunderstood to be a poetry of
“visual” presentation. What Pound had meant by an Image was difficult to
express in literary terms. While the Image for Pound had always been associated
with precision and concreteness of visual presentation, what lay behind the
Image was an idea or an emotion, not a phenomenon in nature, not a naturalistic
fact. The year before Blast Pound had
implied this in “The Serious Artist”:
The serious artist is scientific in
that he presents the image of
his desire of his hate, of his indifference as
precisely that, as
precisely the image of his own desire, hate or indifference.
(The Egoist)
His emphasis, however, had been
misconstrued. “Amygism”—as he was to describe what had happened to Imagism—was
too often a poetic which focused on objects in nature and rendered them
concretely. This was not what Pound meant. Art afforded him a better
vocabulary.
In Lewis’ hard-edge abstraction, Pound saw
what he meant by Image. Pound’s Image, like Lewis’ abstraction, was something
precise that yet stood for a complex of ideas: it did not come from nature but from the mind of the artist.
Rather than the artist being a “Toy of circumstance, as the plastic substance
receiving impression,” Pound, like Lewis, saw the artist “Directing a certain
fluid force against circumstance, as Conceiving instead of merely observing and
reflection” (Pound, “Vortex. Pound," Blast
1, p. 153). Just as for Lewis, what Pound’s artist did was in a realm other
than nature.
For Pound, however, who after all dealing
with language, not with pure form, there is a more vital interrelationship
between nature and art—there is a flow between the two which is absent in
Lewis’ theories. Perhaps Pound’s best statement of this was published the year
after Blast, in “Affirmations”:
The Image can be of two sorts. It can
arise within the mind.
It is then “subjective.” External causes play upon the mind,
perhaps; if so, they are drawn into the mind, fused, transmitted,
and emerge in an
Image unlike themselves. Secondly, the Image
can be objective. Emotion seizing up
some external scene or
action carries it intact in the mind; and that vortex purges
it of all save the essential or dominant or dramatic qualities,
and it emerges like
the external original.
In either case the Image is more
than an idea. It is a vortex
or cluster of fused ideas and is endowed with energy. If
it
does not fulfill these specifications, it is not what I mean
by image. (“Affirmations
[as for Imagisme]” in The New Age)
It is on the basis of these kinds
of statements that we must draw a line between the theories of Lewis and Pound.
Whereas Lewis’ art rejects nature in an attempt to interpret man’s time by
focusing it into space, Pound does not reject nature at all, but would make it
“new”: in Pound’s theory the mind of the artist in conjunction with nature makes something else. This view is
supported by Pound’s attempt to describe how he came to write “In a Station at
the Metro,” a description which appeared in his Gaudier-Brzeska of 1916. His recounting of this process has been so
often reprinted that I will not do so here. The important thing to remember
concerning it is that Pound saw his short “hokku-like
sentences” as a “pattern” or an “abstraction” (“little splotches of colour”) in
a specific impression, and he viewed that “pattern” or “abstraction” as a
record of an interchange between nature and the mind, as an instant “when a
thing outward and objective transform[ed] itself, or dart[ed] into a thing
inward and subjective.”
What is implicit in these comments is that
Pound understood nature and art to be in a dynamic relationship. He stresses,
accordingly, the energy of the vortex, not the stasis at its center:
All experience rushes into this
vortex.
All the energized past, all the past
that is living and worthy
to live. All
MOMENTUM, which is the past
bearing upon us, RACE,
RACE-MEMORY,
Instinct charging the PLACID,
NON-ENERGIZED FUTURE.
(Blast 1, p. 153)
For Pound, “The vortex is the
point of maximum energy,” but that energy is not transformed into space; it is
not Lewis’ stillness. Hence Pound criticizes Futurism not because of its
dynamism, but because of its “disgorging spray,” its “dispersal” of energy.
Cubism, however, is not attacked; indeed, Picasso is named as the father of the
Vortex (Kandinsky as its mother). Somehow, Pound and Lewis—perhaps even
unknowingly—had split along the way in terms of theory.
One can attribute this split in part to
the obvious element that such statements of Pound betray; Pound has an
unswerving faith in a space-time continuum. It is immediately tempting to
connect this with Apollinaire’s “fourth dimension” as described in Le peintres cubists of 1913, and in turn
to relate that to Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity of 1905 and to
Minkowski’s formulation of the space-time continuum in 1908. But, as Linda
Dalrymple Henderson (in her essay “A New Facet on Cubism: ‘The Fourth
Dimension” and ‘Non-Euclidean Geometry’ Reinterpreted,” Art Quarterly, No. 4 [Winter 1971]) has convincingly argued, the
Analytical Cubists most certainly did not have knowledge of these developments
in physics and were more influenced by Riemann and Poincaré’s theories on
non-Euclidean geometry. And as we have seen, Lewis and his Vorticist friends
had not been part of a milieu from which they could have gleaned even that. It
is possible that Lewis had read Apollinaire prior to Blast, for in his statements on Vortex, Lewis attacks what he calls
a “fourth quantity” made up of the Past, the Future and Art (Blast 1, p. 148), but in Pound’s writings there is no mention of any of
these names or concept.
Ironically, Pound arrived at some of his
ideas of space and time, I suggest, through Lewis’ panacea for all the evils of
the age—Henri Bergson. In December 1913 The
New Freewoman—a magazine for which Pound was writing at that time and which
the next year was to become The Egoist—published
a selection from Bergson’s L’Évolution
créatrice entitled “The Philosophy of Ideas.” This essay considers the
problem of man’s perception of movement or evolutionary transition in a world
where all is experienced as durée.
According to Bergson, the problem is that, although man is sensible to the
reality that the world is in flux, in a state of becoming, “the intelligible reality, that which ought to be, is more real still, and
that reality does not change.” In other words
Beneath the qualitative becoming,
beneath the evolutionary
becoming, beneath the extensive becoming, the
mind must
seek that which defines change, the definable quality, the form
of
essence, the end.
Thus, Bergson recognizes the paradox inherent in man’s experience: that he is both a creature of becoming—of pure flux—and of ideas—of something Immutable that seems to be in space. Bergson’s solution is to consider becoming as working in the same way as a cinematographic film, as “a movement hidden in the apparatus and whose function it is to superpose the successive pictures on one another in order to imitate the movement of the real object.” If one looks at reality in this manner, argues Bergson, form becomes inseparable from becoming, which materializes its flow: “Every form thus occupies space, as it occupies time.” And eternity comes to underlie time as a reality.
Pound almost certainly read this essay; he
published an article on Ford Madox Ford in the same issue, and his “The Serious
Artist” had been serialized in the three issues previous. But even if he had
not read it, Bergson’s ideas had achieved popularity throughout Europe. In
fact, as Eugène Minkowski (the phenomenologist, not the physicist) points out, L’Évolution créatrice—and this is
especially evident in this selection—was written partly in an attempt to
counteract Bergson’s initial conception expressed in Time and Free Will (1910), of time and space as dichotomous;
Bergson was reacting to the pressures which Einstein's and Minkowski’s theories
of a space-time continuum had brought to bear (Minkowski, Lived Time).
Even more telling is the
fact that it is impossible to read these words of Bergson without thinking of
Pound’s experiments with hokku and the
Chinese ideogram and his reading—probably in the same year—of the manuscript of
Ernest Fenellosa. Other than serving as a reminder that the Chinese ideogram,
according to Fenellosa, was based on the principle of superimposition of
word-pictures, two short quotations from Fenellosa will be sufficient to show the
relationship of Pound’s Asian studies to the cinematographical metaphor of
Bergson.
The thought-picture is not only
called up by these signs as
well as words, but far more vividly and concretely.
Legs belong
to all three characters: they are alive. The group holds something
of the quality of a continuous
moving picture.
One superiority of verbal poetry as
an art rests on its getting back
to the fundamental reality of time. Chinese poetry has the unique
advantage of combining both elements. It speaks at once with
the vividness of painting, and with the mobility of sounds.
The overlapping of ideas could
not have been missed by a reader as erudite as Pound.
When Pound writes, then, that “Every
concept, every emotion, presents itself to the vivid consciousness in some
primary form,” I believe we must understand him in Bergson’s terms. For Pound,
form is not to be posited as the essence of reality, as it is for Lewis, but as
a reality which, like Picasso’s collages, makes something new that exists in
contiguity with the artist’s time and space. Pound is not against representation
in art. As he was to write later in 1914: “The vorticist can represent or not
as he likes….A resemblance to natural forms is of no consequence one way or the
other (“Edward Wadsworth, Vorticist,” The
Egoist). It is not form that is stressed in Pound’s thinking, but the
consciousness in nature which from either subjective or objective stimuli finds
a form which expresses that stimuli as something new. As late as 1920 Pound was
trying to clarify this notion:
I tried in my early writings on vorticism
to explain how an idea
emerges in the inventive mind, usually, if that
inventive mind be
an artist’s, in some form more sensuous than word-form, in
some form
for which the word or word combination
is not already created.
(“Objectivity,” The Apple)
His simple statement is a long
way from Lewis’ claims that art as pure form is a reality opposed to time and
heedless of nature, and Pound was certainly not unaware of this fact. Indeed,
in the same essay published in The New
Freewoman, Bergson described the futility of trying to work within the
framework of the classical philosophy of ideas, a philosophy which he explains
in terms that come very close to Lewis’ conception of space and time and his
theory of Vorticist art. If Pound read this, as I suggest he must have, the
fact would not have been missed: Bergson was understandably among those
“blasted” in Blast.
One must ask, then, why Pound would give
his name to, and join a group of men led by someone whose theory was in the
long run quite at odds with his own. The answer is rather simple. First of all,
in such a short time neither Lewis nor Pound had yet had a chance to realize
fully their differences. As Cork notes, “Vorticism was never, even at its
inception, a closely-knit movement like Futurism.” What I have shown is seen
from the vantage-point of seven decades, but in 1914 the Vorticists’ theories
had not yet been fully expressed, even to themselves. Moreover, the two men did
have much in common: the belief in the artist as a serious creator who worked
on a level above the minds of most men, and an outspoken contempt for much art
and literature of the recent and often not-so-recent past. Both were
missionaries who found in Vorticism a name that would give attention to their
shared and their individual causes. Perhaps they never imaged that they needed
to share a unified theory. As Lewis later wrote of Pound and his relationship
to Vorticism:
Ezra Pound attached himself to the
Blast Group. That group was
composed of people all very “extremist” in their
views. In the matter
of fine art, as distinct from literature, it was their policy
to admit
no artist disposed to technical compromise, as they regarded it.
What
struck them principally about Pound was that his fire-eating
propagandist
utterances were not accompanied by any very ex-
perimental efforts in his particular
medium. His poetry, to the
minds of the more fanatical of the group, was a
series of pastiches
of old french or old italian poetry, and could lay no
claim to
participate in the new burst of art in progress. Its novelty
consisted
largely in the distance it went back,
not forward; in
archaism, not new
creation. That was how they regarded Pound’s
literary contributions. But this
certain discrepancy between what
Pound said—what he supported and held up as an
example—
and what he did, was striking enough to impress itself on anybody.”
(Lewis, Time and Western Man)
Again, what Lewis most shows us
here is what he failed to understand in Picasso’s collages: that Pound was
using the past as Picasso had used the bits and pieces of cloth and glass from
nature to create something new which would exist simultaneously in time and
space. Pound, on his part, expressed the differences between himself and Lewis
in a slightly more philosophical manner: “The Vorticism movement is a movement
of individuals, for the protection of individuality. Humanity has been
interesting, more interesting than the rest of the animal kingdom because the
individual has been more easily discernible from the herd.” This emphatic
individualism is something that we must take into account when we discuss
Vorticism. Richard Cook’s excellent book and show have demonstrated this; but
both would have been strengthened if Cork had more fully investigated the
differences of theory which lay behind Vorticist art.
College Park, Maryland, 1976
Reprinted
from The Art Quarterly (Metropolitan
Museum of Art), I, Autumn 1978
No comments:
Post a Comment